The Panentheism of Karl Christian Friedrich Krause (1781-1832)
From Transcendental Philosophy to Metaphysics
Summary
Excerpt
Table Of Contents
- Cover
- Title
- Copyright
- About the author
- About the book
- This eBook can be cited
- Table of Contents
- Preface
- 1. The Life of Karl Christian Friedrich Krause
- 1.1 Krause’s childhood and education
- 1.2 Krause’s years as Privatdozent in Jena
- 1.3 The restless years and Schopenhauer as a neighbour
- 1.4 Krause’s last years in Göttingen and Munich
- I. The Panentheism of Karl Christian Friedrich Krause
- 2. Overview: The Panentheism of Karl Christian Friedrich Krause
- 2.1 The system of science
- 2.2 The analytical-ascending part of science
- 2.3 The intuition of God as the ultimate ground
- 2.4 The synthetical-descending part of science
- 2.5 Krause’s argument for panentheism: God in Himself
- 3. The Method and Structure of Science
- 3.1 Science as an organic system and the principle of science
- 3.2 Science and intellectual intuition
- 3.3 The analytical-ascending part of science
- 3.4 The synthetical-descending part of science
- 3.5 Summary
- 4. Science and the Constitution of the Ego as such
- 4.1 The fundamental intuition of the ego
- 4.2 The material constitution of the ego as such
- 4.3 The formal constitution of the ego as such
- 4.4 The material-formal categories of the ego as such
- 4.5 The immediate certainty of Krause’s intuition of the categories
- 4.6 Summary
- 5. Nature, Reason, and the Ego in Itself
- 5.1 The ego as body and mind
- 5.2 The ego as a body
- 5.3 The ego as a mind
- 5.4 The ego as a human being
- 5.5 Nature and reason
- 5.6 Nature, reason, humanity, and the concept of the world
- 5.7 Summary
- 6. The Fundamental Intuition of God
- 6.1 Knowledge as a trinary relation
- 6.2 God as the ultimate ground of all things
- 6.3 The ubiquity of the formal and material categories
- 6.4 The fundamental intuition of God
- 6.5 The coherence of the fundamental intuition of God
- 6.6 The circularity of arguments for the existence of God
- 6.7 Orwesen as the one subject and object of knowledge and being
- 6.8 Summary
- 7. The Essence of God as such
- 7.1 Orwesen and the material categories
- 7.2 Orwesen and the formal categories
- 7.3 Orwesen and the material-formal categories
- 7.4 Summary
- 8. The Case for Panentheism
- 8.1 Unity and difference
- 8.2 The world as the unity of reason and nature
- 8.3 The case for panentheism
- 8.4 Krause’s panentheism and Creatio ex nihilo
- 8.5 Summary
- 9. The Organic System of Science
- 9.1 The organic system of science as the science of Orwesen
- 9.2 The infinity of the system of science
- 9.3 The principal sciences and the system of science
- 9.4 The non-vicious circularity of the system of science
- 9.5 Summary
- II. The Importance of Karl Christian Friedrich Krause’s Panentheism
- 10. Krause’s Influence on Arthur Schopenhauer
- 10.1 Historical evidence for Krause’s influence on Schopenhauer
- 10.2 Systematic evidence for Krause’s influence on Schopenhauer
- 10.3 Summary
- 11. Krause Importance for Philosophy of Religion
- 11.1 Krause and analytic philosophy
- 11.2 Concepts of God in philosophy of religion
- 11.3 The adequacy of Krause’s concept of God
- 11.4 The importance of Krause’s arguments for panentheism
- 11.5 The interaction between God and the world on Krause’s panentheism
- 11.6 Summary
- 12. Krause’s Importance for Philosophy of Science
- 12.1 Concepts of science in philosophy of science
- 12.2 The plausibility of Krause’s concept of science
- 12.3 Reductionism, holism and the organic system of science
- 12.4 Ultimate explanation and intellectual intuition
- 12.5 Summary
- 13. Krause’s Importance for Philosophy of Mind
- 13.1 Panpsychism in the philosophy of mind
- 13.2 Arguments for panpsychism
- 13.3 Arguments against panpsychism
- 13.4 Krause’s panentheism and panpsychism
- 13.5 Summary
- 14. Closing Assessment
- Bibliography
- Index
- Series index
Karl Christian Friedrich Krause left an impressive oeuvre consisting of 256 books and articles, covering most branches of philosophy, the humanities, and science (cf. Ureña 2007: xv).1 His Vorlesungen über das System der Philosophie and his Vorlesungen über die Grundwahrheiten der Wissenschaft are his most important books for philosophy. Through Julián Sanz del Río he has gained considerable popularity in Spain and Latin-America, where his philosophy goes by the name ‘Krausismo’ and he is sometimes claimed as the greatest German idealist.2
In recent Anglo-Saxon philosophy, he is known mainly for devising the term ‘panentheism’.3 Understanding of Krause is impressionistic, contains mistakes, and is incomplete. For example, it is said that his philosophy is ‘mystical and spiritualistic’ (Zweig 1967: 363), that he was ‘an obscure […] figure’ (McInnes 1967: 514) who ‘expressed himself in an artificial and often unfathomable vocabulary which included […] monstrous neologisms ← 11 | 12 → […] which are untranslatable into German, let alone English’ (Zweig 1967: 363). It is said that he was ‘under the influence […] of Schelling’ (Zweig 1967: 363) and ‘a student of Hegel’ (Hartshorne 1987: 169).
However, it is straightforwardly false that Krause was a student of Hegel or that, apart from his first years as a student in Jena, he was under the influence of Schelling. Hegel and Krause have been colleagues for some time in Jena, lecturing at the same time. As Krause (1890: 16) states: ‘Fries and Hegel knew me personally, and I lectured simultaneously with them in Jena in the years 1802–1804’. And although Krause attended some of Schelling’s lectures he did not like either them or Schelling much: ‘I like Schlegel very much, but not Schelling’ (Krause 1903: 7) and ‘in [Schelling’s] philosophy of nature I find propositions, which I already discovered for myself, following Fichte’s system’ (Krause 1903: 11). Furthermore, it is inadequate to characterize his philosophy as mystical or obscure. One might wonder how such statements could be justified, given that there are no English translations of Krause’s relevant works, and even the German works are hardly ever cited.4 It is true that Krause’s philosophy is demanding due to the style of his writing and the neologisms he introduced, but so are Hegel and Heidegger.
Krause saw himself, like many of his colleagues, as the real successor of Kant. As Krause (1890: 143/144) states: ‘I can actually be regarded as Kant’s first successor, but I was so original, self-sufficient without intending it; that what appears as a continuation of Kant, was already the main thing I completed in 1803. This was before I was able to completely look at the relation of my own research and work to the Kantian, because I had then read and thought through Kant’s writings only very little. Rather, the main teachings of my system, completed in the years 1805 and 1806, were the key to the Kantian quest and made it possible for me to understand and appreciate the Kantian project from the highest standpoint.’
The key and main teaching of Krause is that the theory of categories should be understood not as a system of pure concepts of the understanding, which can be applied only to temporal individuals, but as a system of ideas ← 12 | 13 → of reason, which Krause develops in the form of panentheism. According to Krause: ‘Kant considered the categories merely as finite concepts of the understanding, and they can only be considered as applicable to temporal sense perception. Therefore, he says explicitly that they are not rational concepts of ideas of reason [Vernunftbegriffe der Vernunftideen], because, rather, an idea of reason is an infinitely extended category’ (Krause 1869: 228). However, on Krause’s view, nothing counts against the proposition that the categories are, pace Kant, ideas of reason, and he seeks to show that we apply the categories both to the finite temporal given, and to the infinite unconditioned. Because, in his view, Krause is able to show that, through the intuition of the essence and existence of God, the ideas of reason turn out to denote, or even be, properties of the divine unity, he therefore thinks he has achieved the most important task of philosophy as defined by Kant: ‘“Whether the ideas of reason behave towards the categories (his highest concepts of the understanding) as the categories to sensibility” […] I have now solved this problem raised by Kant, without my knowing, at the time, that Kant posed this problem; and it was by using Kant’s critical method in a completely independent way, in the course of my own philosophical research. My lectures on the system of philosophy include the complete development of the doctrine [Organismus] of the categories as unconditional, and infinite, divine, essentialities [Wesenheiten], or as attributes of God’ (Krause 1889: 312).
According to Krause, his panentheistic system of philosophy, in effect, provides the understanding of the possibility of Being and knowing, taking into account the interrelations of the transcendental and transcendent categories. Krause’s system is concerned with the understanding of reality, as such, from the unity of its ultimate ground and highest principle: Whoever knows God knows the unity of the categories of Being and knowing in their origin, and thereby knows that God is the necessary and sufficient condition for both our knowledge of reality, and the very fact that the world is and exists as it does.
Precisely because of this, Krause perceived his own system of philosophy as a successful combination of Platonic metaphysics and Kantian transcendental philosophy: Krause’s panentheism provides a metaphysical theory about the fundamental structure of empirical reality in terms of reality’s ultimate cause or highest principle based on reflections on the transcendental constitution ← 13 | 14 → of the ego, that is, based on reflections on the conditions for the possibility that the ego perceives empirical reality as it does. As Krause states: ‘We are convinced that in our system, the principles of which have been repeatedly described by us, and the partial execution of which we have published in a series of works, the task of scientific research and scientific education [Wissenschaftsforschung und Wissenschaftsbildung], in its main points, is satisfactorily carried out. For, inasmuch as the recognition and acknowledgment of the principle of science is gained by the analytic-subjective self-knowledge of the mind, the whole structure of science can be pictured in law-like and organic progress. And so the task of Socrates and Plato, as well as Kant, Fichte, and Schelling, is generally solved’ (Krause 1889a: 478).5
In what follows, I will concentrate on the justification and clarification of Krause’s panentheistic philosophy of science that arguable stands at the centre of Krause’s philosophy. After a brief biographical note on Krause’s life I will first elaborate Krause’s panentheism in Chapters 2–9 before I turn to Krause’s influence on Schopenhauer in Chapter 10. Chapters 11–14 analyse the importance of Krause’s system of philosophy for recent debates in the philosophy of religion, philosophy of science, and philosophy of mind. As we will see, Krause is still a valuable source of insight for recent philosophical debates.
I am most grateful to Professor Stephen Priest of the University of Oxford for his enormous help with the translation. Without his philosophical acumen and linguistic sensitivity, Krause’s sometimes idiosyncratic way of philosophizing would have remained untranslated. I am further grateful to Samuel Hughes of the University of Cambridge, who critically read the penultimate version, and to Siegfried Pflegerl. Any remaining mistakes are, of course, my own.
1 Throughout this book the following rule applies with regard to quotations: if the quoted passage is originally in German, then an English translation will normally be provided, while the reference will be to the German original.
2 Cf. Zweig (1967: 365): ‘Krause’s philosophy, while not very influential in Germany, found considerable support in Spain, where, for a time, “Krausism” flourished. This was largely due to the efforts of Julian Sanz del Rio, the minister of culture, who visited Germany and Belgium in 1844 and came into contact with a number of Krause’s disciples, notably Heinrich Ahrens in Brussels and Hermann von Leonhardi in Heidelberg.’ Cf. also McInnes (1967: 514): ‘Spanish Krausism was less a philosophy than a cult, a rationalist religion that can be regarded as a forerunner of the Modernist movement in Catholicism. Its adherents behaved like members of Freemasonry, and it is doubtful whether many of them understood Sanz del Rio’s obscure books on his even more obscure master [Krause].’
3 Cf. Cooper (2006: 26): ‘Panentheism literally means ‘all-in-God-ism’. This is the Greek-English translation of the German term Allingottlehre, ‘the doctrine that all is in god.’ It was coined by Karl Krause (1781–1832), a contemporary of Schleiermacher, Schelling, and Hegel, to distinguish his own theology from both classical theism and pantheism.’ Cf. also Gregersen (2004: 27/8): ‘The very term ‘panentheism’ was coined as late as 1829 by the post-Kantian philosopher and mystic Karl Christian Friedrich Krause (1781–1832)’. Cf. also Hartshorne (1987: 168) and Palmquist (2008: 19).
4 According to Ureña (2007: lxx) there are only two translations of Krause’s work into English. The first one is The Ideal of Humanity and Universal Federation. A Contribution to Social Philosophy, ed. W. Hastie (Edinburgh: T. & T. Clark, 1900). The second one is The Family: A Pansophic Ideal. (Willits: Calif, 1933).
5 Furthermore, as Krause (1890: 13) says: ‘Because my system, throughout, from its very first seed, is cultivated in independent, self-sufficient, research, and in the formation of the pure and fully grasped principle of science, it has not departed from this, and could not depart from this, to approximate to some other philosophical system, or unite itself to already existing conflicting systems. But, among other old tasks, that of liberating Platonism and Aristotelianism from their one-sidedness, and unifying them by means of their opposing essentials has also come to pass, as the main thing; but as far as that task has its meaning as a repetition of the Kantian task but at a higher level, and as the dissolution of the latter.’
1. The Life of Karl Christian Friedrich Krause
Karl Christian Friedrich Krause dedicated his life solely to his philosophical ideals, and lived according to their practical consequences, without regard to his own well-being. Because of this principled, even unreasonable, stubbornness, Krause can be understood as the tragic hero of his own philosophy, who never wanted to adapt to existing social expectations, and needed all his energy to work through them: ‘I know the world as it should be, and, in fact, it’s worth a little trouble to find it as it is; at least I would find each constellation only too often, as it should not be. […] I know, in some eyes I judge and I act wrongly; only this is however better than to be a fool in one’s own eyes. I act as I think it is reasonable and am full of confidence for the future; because I know what can be robbed from me and what not’ (cited in Kodalle 1985: 272).6
Details
- Pages
- 260
- Publication Year
- 2018
- ISBN (PDF)
- 9783631746905
- ISBN (ePUB)
- 9783631746912
- ISBN (MOBI)
- 9783631746929
- ISBN (Hardcover)
- 9783631746899
- DOI
- 10.3726/b13320
- Open Access
- CC-BY-NC-ND
- Language
- English
- Publication date
- 2018 (December)
- Keywords
- Holism Panpsychism Metaphysical grounding German idealism Analytic theology
- Published
- Berlin, Bern, Bruxelles, New York, Oxford, Warszawa, Wien, 2018. 258pp., 4 tables, 7 graphs
- Product Safety
- Peter Lang Group AG